Coercion: container, contents and measure readings

Similar documents
Slides and handout can be downloaded from: sfb991.uni-duesseldorf.de/c09/slides/

Portion Readings are Count Readings, not Measure Readings

Semantic Web. Ontology Engineering. Gerd Gröner, Matthias Thimm. Institute for Web Science and Technologies (WeST) University of Koblenz-Landau

Introduction to the Practical Exam Stage 1. Presented by Amy Christine MW, DC Flynt MW, Adam Lapierre MW, Peter Marks MW

Introduction to the Practical Exam Stage 1

Better Punctuation Prediction with Hierarchical Phrase-Based Translation

Restructuring non-finite verb clusters in Dutch

Noun-Verb Decomposition

EMC Publishing s C est à toi! 3, 2E Correlated to the Colorado World Language Frameworks French 3

Structures of Life. Investigation 1: Origin of Seeds. Big Question: 3 rd Science Notebook. Name:

Mastering Measurements

Corpus analysis. Alessia Cadeddu. This analysis has been carried out on a corpus of dessert recipes taken from the Internet.

STA Module 6 The Normal Distribution

STA Module 6 The Normal Distribution. Learning Objectives. Examples of Normal Curves

Buying Filberts On a Sample Basis

Decision making with incomplete information Some new developments. Rudolf Vetschera University of Vienna. Tamkang University May 15, 2017

Title: Farmers Growing Connections (anytime in the year)

FOR PERSONAL USE. Capacity BROWARD COUNTY ELEMENTARY SCIENCE BENCHMARK PLAN ACTIVITY ASSESSMENT OPPORTUNITIES. Grade 3 Quarter 1 Activity 2

Chapter 3: Labor Productivity and Comparative Advantage: The Ricardian Model

Objective: Decompose a liter to reason about the size of 1 liter, 100 milliliters, 10 milliliters, and 1 milliliter.

Social Media: Content Drives Community Groups

Density Gradient Column Lab

Word order in measure phrases in Malagasy dialects

Feasibility Project for Store Brand Macaroni and Cheese

Grade 5 / Scored Student Samples ITEM #5 SMARTER BALANCED PERFORMANCE TASK

-SQA- SCOTTISH QUALIFICATIONS AUTHORITY NATIONAL CERTIFICATE MODULE: UNIT SPECIFICATION GENERAL INFORMATION. -Module Number Session

Testing Taste. FRAMEWORK I. Scientific and Engineering Practices 1,3,4,6,7,8 II. Cross-Cutting Concepts III. Physical Sciences

Ditransitive constructions in Vietnamese: How to integrate serial verb constructions in a typology of alignment patterns

MBA 503 Final Project Guidelines and Rubric

IMSI Annual Business Meeting Amherst, Massachusetts October 26, 2008

1. Title: Identification of High Yielding, Root Rot Tolerant Sweet Corn Hybrids

Is Fair Trade Fair? ARKANSAS C3 TEACHERS HUB. 9-12th Grade Economics Inquiry. Supporting Questions

LEVEL: BEGINNING HIGH

The Effect of Almond Flour on Texture and Palatability of Chocolate Chip Cookies. Joclyn Wallace FN 453 Dr. Daniel

THE WINEMAKER S TOOL KIT UCD V&E: Recognizing Non-Microbial Taints; May 18, 2017

Gasoline Empirical Analysis: Competition Bureau March 2005

Flavour Legislation Past Present and Future or From the Stone Age to the Internet Age and Beyond. Joy Hardinge

What s the Best Way to Evaluate Benefits or Claims? Silvena Milenkova SVP of Research & Strategic Direction

APPENDIX PROPER USE GUIDELINES INGREDIENT BRANDING

EFFECT OF TOMATO GENETIC VARIATION ON LYE PEELING EFFICACY TOMATO SOLUTIONS JIM AND ADAM DICK SUMMARY

The challenge of tackling Campylobacter in Belgium

STUDY REGARDING THE RATIONALE OF COFFEE CONSUMPTION ACCORDING TO GENDER AND AGE GROUPS

Grade: Kindergarten Nutrition Lesson 4: My Favorite Fruits

STABILITY IN THE SOCIAL PERCOLATION MODELS FOR TWO TO FOUR DIMENSIONS

Pizza Ontology. a review of core concepts for building a pizza ontology

A Note on a Test for the Sum of Ranksums*

WTO Agreement on Import Licensing Procedures. An Overview

QUALITY DESCRIPTOR / REPRESENTATIONS GUIDELINES FOR THE

A New Approach for Smoothing Soil Grain Size Curve Determined by Hydrometer

VIII. Claim Drafting Methodologies. Becky White

The Roles of Social Media and Expert Reviews in the Market for High-End Goods: An Example Using Bordeaux and California Wines

Fedima Position Paper on Labelling of Allergens

5. Supporting documents to be provided by the applicant IMPORTANT DISCLAIMER

Recent U.S. Trade Patterns (2000-9) PP542. World Trade 1929 versus U.S. Top Trading Partners (Nov 2009) Why Do Countries Trade?

Only the Dark Knight is free to choose. Stephen Crain, Aijun Huang, Haiquan Huang & Peng Zhou

Produce basic hot and cold desserts

Activity 7.3 Comparing the density of different liquids

CAUTION!!! Do not eat anything (Skittles, cylinders, dishes, etc.) associated with the lab!!!

To study the effects of four different levels of fertilizer NPK nutrients, applied at a ratio of N:P 2

What Is This Module About?

UNIT TITLE: MANAGE AND OPERATE A COFFEE SHOP NOMINAL HOURS: 85

Wine-Tasting by Numbers: Using Binary Logistic Regression to Reveal the Preferences of Experts

Parsnip Pancakes Revised By Mikaela Taylor, FoodCorps

Fairtrade Buying Behaviour: We Know What They Think, But Do We Know What They Do?

Rituals on the first of the month Laurie and Winifred Bauer

Jure Leskovec, Computer Science Dept., Stanford

Please be sure to save a copy of this activity to your computer!

Please sign and date here to indicate that you have read and agree to abide by the above mentioned stipulations. Student Name #4

Effect of paraquat and diquat applied preharvest on canola yield and seed quality

The amount of fruit you need to eat depends on age, sex, and level of physical activity. Recommended daily amounts are shown in the chart.

International Journal of Wine Business Research: Background and How to Get Published. Professor Johan Bruwer. (Editor-in-Chief)

Experiment 2: ANALYSIS FOR PERCENT WATER IN POPCORN

Yelp Chanllenge. Tianshu Fan Xinhang Shao University of Washington. June 7, 2013

Union Authorisation. Gosia Oledzka. A.I.S.E. Bratislava May Scientific and Technical Affairs Manager

O N E S YO U L L E AT! LESSON 2 & FRUITS ARE THE

Adapted By Kennda Lynch, Elizabeth Adsit and Kathy Zook July 26, Moooooogic!

Structural Reforms and Agricultural Export Performance An Empirical Analysis

The Bottled Water Scam

SPLENDID SOIL (1 Hour) Addresses NGSS Level of Difficulty: 2 Grade Range: K-2

Evaluation of desiccants to facilitate straight combining canola. Brian Jenks North Dakota State University

Lollapalooza Did Not Attend (n = 800) Attended (n = 438)

International Journal of Business and Commerce Vol. 3, No.8: Apr 2014[01-10] (ISSN: )

Napa County Planning Commission Board Agenda Letter

(Definition modified from APSnet)

Effect of paraquat and diquat applied preharvest on canola yield and seed quality

Fijian Verbs of Cooking. Sereana Usuramo

A Comparison of Approximate Bayesian Bootstrap and Weighted Sequential Hot Deck for Multiple Imputation

Bishop Druitt College Food Technology Year 10 Semester 2, 2018

BREWERS ASSOCIATION CRAFT BREWER DEFINITION UPDATE FREQUENTLY ASKED QUESTIONS. December 18, 2018

Napa County Planning Commission Board Agenda Letter

Instruction (Manual) Document

Materials and Methods

7-DAY HYDRATION CHALLENGE

Contesting the Meaning of Fair Trade Policy and Practice:

UNIT TITLE: PROVIDE ADVICE TO PATRONS ON FOOD AND BEVERAGE SERVICES NOMINAL HOURS: 80

Suitability for Haul Roads (MI) Macomb County, Michigan, and Oakland County, Michigan (River Bends Park, West Side, Shelby Twp.)

MEAT WEBQUEST Foods and Nutrition

Recipe Adjustment Factor Method

Sponsored by: Center For Clinical Investigation and Cleveland CTSC

Online Appendix to. Are Two heads Better Than One: Team versus Individual Play in Signaling Games. David C. Cooper and John H.

Transcription:

Coercion: container, contents and measure readings Peter Sutton & Hana Filip Heinrich Heine University, Düsseldorf Workshop on Approaches to Coercion and Polysemy University of Oslo November, 2017 Download these slides from: sfb991.uni-duesseldorf.de/en/c09/slides/

Outline Introduction and plan Small case study: wine and beer Analysis Structure of pseudo-partitive NPs Semantic analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs in TTR CD + Mass Noun expressions: why are measure readings (usually) blocked

Data 1: Readings of pseudo-partitive NPs Pseudo-partitive NPs such as two glasses of wine have at least 3 interpretations: (1) a. He turned to reach the two glasses of wine that stood on a bedside table. (BNC) b. i (sic.) should set the record straight with Clayart that two glasses of red wine a day have beneficial health results. [UKWaC] c. Two glasses of wine is equal to 3 standard drinks of any alcoholic beverage. [UKWaC] (1a) has a container reading: the verbs, reach, stand, select for solid objects, e.g., containers (glasses), not the contents (wine) (1b) has a contents reading: plural agreement, the contents (wine) of exactly two glasses has the effect on health, not the containers (1c) has a measure reading: singular agreement, the equivalence is between volume or alcoholic content of the totality of alcoholic beverage contained in the relevant containers 1/25 Container, contents and measures

Data 2: CD+Mass N constructions Type mismatch between Cardinal (CD) numerical and Mass Noun (Mass N) prompts a mass-to-count shift ( CD as in Penn Treebank tags): We get two different coerced mass-to-count shifts associated with constructions like two wines: (2) a. Winnie returned, with two wines, which was just as well as Rab had all but drained her glass. [BNC] b. At the rehearsal dinner I fake-drank two wines, slowly pouring them into other people s glasses when they weren t looking. (2a) container reading: returned, with two wines evokes implicit containers two glasses containing wine (2b) contents reading: pour selects liquid (therefore contents). Plural agreement. two portions of wine, each the contents of a glass. Measure readings are hard to get (none in BNC or UKWaC). (3) # Two wines is equal to 3 standard drinks of any alcoholic beverage. Nb: Actually, for wine and beer, sentences expressing subkinds are far more common (two wines were served with dinner: a Malbec and a Sauvignon.) 2/25 Container, contents and measures

Summary: Pseudo-partitive NPs such as two glasses of wine have at least 3 interpretations: Container Contents Measure Novel observation: For pseudo-partitive NPs (two wines), coercively re-interpreted with an implicit classifier-like concept (two glasses of wine), it is much harder (if at all possible) to get measure interpretations. Our main question: Why can t we get measure interpretations for two wines? What is it about measure interpretations that makes them so hard to access when coercing a mass N into a count interpretation? 3/25 Container, contents and measures

Plan Some empirical background. A (very) preliminary corpus study. An analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs using TTR (Cooper, 2012, a.m.o) Basic idea: Measure interpretations are derived from contents interpretations. An analysis of CD+Mass-N phrases: A type clash between a CD and a mass N triggers either: (1) A shifted count interpretation (container with mass N contents) (2) A shifted count interpretation (some apportioned contents, held in a container) Either (1) or (2) resolve the type clash. So usually no driving factor to coerce (2) into a measure interpretation But there can be such a driving factor (e.g., SG agreement: two wines is equal to...). So, a contents-to-measure shifted interpretation is in principle available. But it is not usually available in practice. Reason: high processing burden on agents. Two shifts required to derive the requisite measure interpretation (mass-to-count/contents shift and a count-to-mass/measure shift) 4/25 Container, contents and measures

Outline Introduction and plan Small case study: wine and beer Analysis Structure of pseudo-partitive NPs Semantic analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs in TTR CD + Mass Noun expressions: why are measure readings (usually) blocked

Pilot BNC corpus study Two target Ns: wine and beer Two contexts: 1. Part of a measure phrase with a classifier-like head N e.g. glass, bottle. Four glasses of red wine. Two bottles of beer. 2. Directly modified by a CD ( cardinality ) expression Four red wines. Two beers. Resulting data hand-annotated with different readings. 5/25 Container, contents and measures

Search criteria and frequencies: Full NPs: [tag="cd"] [tag="jj"]* [lemma="glass bottle jug pitcher can"] [word="of"] [tag="jj"]* [tag="nn NNS" & lemma="beer"] [tag="cd"] [tag="jj"]* [lemma="glass"] [word="of"] [tag="jj"]* [tag="nn NNS" & lemma="wine"] CD+Mass-N: [tag="cd"] [tag="jj"]* [tag="nns" & lemma="beer"] [tag="cd"] [tag="jj"]* [tag="nns" & lemma="wine"] Frequencies: Full NPs CD+Mass-N Total beer 13 20 33 wine 37 35 72 Total 50 55 105 6/25 Container, contents and measures

Results Readings for beer (%) Full NP CD+Mass-N Subkind 0 60 Contents 46 10 Container 46 30 Measure 8 0 Readings for wine (%) Full NP CD+Mass-N Subkind 0 91 Contents 29.7 3 Container 56.8 6 Measure 13.5 0 Readings collated (%) Full NP CD+Mass-N Subkind 0 80 Contents 34 5 Container 54 15 Measure 12 0 Full pseudo-partitive NP Mostly contents and container readings No kind readings (not surprising) Relatively few measure readings CD+Mass-N Vast majority kind readings No measure readings beer vs. wine Easier to coerce beer into container/contents readings 7/25 Container, contents and measures

Discussion Measure readings are witnessed in pseudo-partitive NPs formed with classifier-like expressions. No evidence of measure readings of CD + Mass-N expressions. But more data needed. In general, constructed examples are pretty bad. Compare: (4) a. Two wines is equal to 3 standard drinks of any alcoholic beverage or any snack food that contains about 200 calories, such as 40 grams of chocolate. b. Two glasses of wine is equal to 3 standard drinks of any alcoholic beverage or any snack food that contains about 200 calories, such as 40 grams of chocolate. [UKWaC] 8/25 Container, contents and measures

Outline Introduction and plan Small case study: wine and beer Analysis Structure of pseudo-partitive NPs Semantic analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs in TTR CD + Mass Noun expressions: why are measure readings (usually) blocked

Outline Introduction and plan Small case study: wine and beer Analysis Structure of pseudo-partitive NPs Semantic analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs in TTR CD + Mass Noun expressions: why are measure readings (usually) blocked

Rothstein s syntactic analysis Landman (2003), Rothstein (2011) (i.a.): Numerical expressions in number marking languages can be NP modifiers. Freely licensed shift, approx: n e, t, e, t Rothstein (2011) argues for a syntactic distinction between container readings and measure readings (does not analyse contents readings): Container Measure Container reading much like a CD + Count-N structure, but with a complex NP (glasses of wine). Measure reading formed from a measure (three glasses) and an argument (wine) 9/25 Container, contents and measures

Our analysis: container/contents readings Adopt (roughly) Rothstein s analysis for direct numerical modification and container readings. Same syntax for contents reading (different semantics). np np numdet np numdet np num n num n pp three glasses three glasses of wine 10/25 Container, contents and measures

Our analysis continued: Measure readings 1 Reject Rothstein s analysis of measure NPs Tagline: Extensive measure functions are not expressed only by classifier-like N predicates like glass alone: (4b) Two glasses of wine is equal to 3 standard drinks of any alcoholic beverage or any snack food that contains about 200 calories, such as 40 grams of chocolate. [UKWaC] Measures are formed from e.g., glass of wine, not just containers, e.g., glass alone, to make the relevant different dimensions for measurement accessible. The contents of the glass matters (not just the container), because we can measure relative to different dimensions of the contents; for wine, the relevant dimension is not only volume (based on the container, e.g., glass alone), but also calories (4b), units of alcohol, volume,... You can t ask: how many calories is the contents of a glass (punkt)? You can ask: how many calories is the contents of a glass of wine? 11/25 Container, contents and measures

Our analysis continued: Measure readings 2 (4b) Two glasses of wine is equal to 3 standard drinks of any alcoholic beverage or any snack food that contains about 200 calories, such as 40 grams of chocolate. [UKWaC] In (4b), reading is: 2 (measure in calories(content(glass of wine))) I.e. Measure readings are derived from (intensionalised) contents readings Rothstein s analysis: Our analysis: measurenp num two measure np n glasses of pp wine 12/25 Container, contents and measures

Summary Direct counting numdet np np Numerical shifted to NP modifier. num n Container and contents readings Measure readings numdet num three num two three np n glasses measurenp n glasses glasses np of measure np of pp pp wine wine Numerical shifted to NP modifier. CL-like N shifted to either container or contents interpretation. Numerical denotes a numeral. Contents reading of NP shifted to a contextually salient measure over the relevant dimension. 13/25 Container, contents and measures

Outline Introduction and plan Small case study: wine and beer Analysis Structure of pseudo-partitive NPs Semantic analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs in TTR CD + Mass Noun expressions: why are measure readings (usually) blocked

Count nouns and plural count nouns Functions from records to record types [x : Ind] RecType (abbreviation: Ppty) Record argument must be a witness to an individual (or plural individual ( Ind)) and a context (Cxt) Contexts, here, are individuating contexts: provide individuation schemas Cxt abbreviates (x : Ind PType) (x : Ind PType) Record type contains the counting base property (labelled p cbase ) An the application conditions (labelled s app ) [ ] x: Ind p cbase =λr : [y : Ind] [ s 1 : r.c(glass)(r.y) ] : Ppty glass =λr :. c: Cxt s app : [ s 2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) ] glasses =λr : [ x: Ind c: Cxt ] p cbase =λr : [y : Ind] [ s 1 :r.c(glass)(r.y) ] : Ppty. s app : [ s 2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) ] 14/25 Container, contents and measures

Numerical expressions and the NMOD shift Numerical expressions interpreted as record types. E.g. the type of witnesses for the singleton type of real numbers equal to 3 NMOD shifts such types to a Ppty modifier The effect: to add a condition that the argument individual has some cardinality relative to the counting base property. The counting base property is needed (if x = 52cards, then Card(x,card cbase,52), but Card(x,deck cbase,1)) (Link, 1983) three = [ n=3 : R ] [ ] x: NMOD = λr :[n : R] λp :Ppty λr : Ind. [ c: Cxt ] N type=p(r): RecType s : Card(r.x, P(r).p cbase, R.n) [ ] x: NMOD( three )= λp :Ppty λr : Ind. [ c: Cxt ] N type=p(r): RecType s : Card(r.x, P(r).p cbase, 3) 15/25 Container, contents and measures

Direct counting with lexically simple count Ns np NMOD( three ) = λp :Ppty λr : [ x: Ind c: Cxt ] [ N type=p(r): RecType. s card : Card(r.x, P, 3) ] numdet three glasses [ ] x: = λr : Ind p cbase =λr : [y : Ind] [ s 1 :r.c(glass)(r.y) ] : Ppty. c: Cxt [ s app : s2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) ] NMOD( three )( glasses ) [ ] p x: = λr : cbase =λr : [y : Ind][s 1 :r.c(glass)(r.y)] : Ppty Ind N type= s c: Cxt app : [ s 2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) ] s card : Card(r.x, N type.p cbase, 3) num np n glasses : RecType After flattening and relabelling: [ ] p x: = λr : cbase =λr : [y : Ind][s 1 :r.c(glass)(r.y)] : Ppty Ind. s c: Cxt app : [ s 2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) ] s card : Card(r.x, p cbase, 3) 16/25 Container, contents and measures

Count nouns versus mass nouns As we have argued elsewhere (i.a. Sutton and Filip, 2016b,a) Mass noun lexical entries specify a null counting context (an individuation schema that allows overlap). Overlap in counting bases makes counting go wrong (Landman, 2011) also assume a type Subst (not all mass nouns denote substances, however) Suppress details here. Main idea: If c : Cxt o, c(p) applies to an individual a iff, for some c : Cxt, c (P)(a). a must belong to some individuating partition of the domain of P If different, overlapping partitions are allowable, then evaluation at the null counting context allows them all in. glass =λr : [ x: Ind c: Cxt ]. wine =λr : [ x: ] Subst. p cbase =λr : [y : Ind] [ s 1 : r.c(glass)(r.y) ] : Ppty s app : [ s 2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) ] c : Cxt 0 p cbase =λr : [y : Ind] [ s 1 : c(wine)(r.y) ] : Ppty s app = [ s 2 : c(wine)(r.x) ] 17/25 Container, contents and measures

Container shifts One of two shifts licensed (in English), by of in pseudo-partitives (or by intonation as in Three boxes [pause] tomatoes). { ofcontainer of = of contents [ x: Ind c: Cxt of container = λp :Ppty λq :Ppty λr : N type=p(r) : RecType [ ] z : par : Ind Subst c : Cxt 0 s in.vessel : P(r).s app Q(par).s app [s contain : contain.each(r.x, par.z)] After some steps of flattening and relabelling: glasses of container wine = p cbase =λr :[y : Ind].[s 1 :r.c(glass)(r.y)] : Ppty [ ] [ ] z : x: λr : par : Ind Subst Ind c : Cxt 0. c: Cxt s 2 : r.c(glass)(r.x) s in.vessel : s 3 : par.c(wine)(par.z) s contain : contain.each(r.x, par.z) I.e. Glasses that contain wine 18/25 Container, contents and measures ].

Contents shifts The other of two shifts licensed (in English), by of in pseudo-partitives (or by intonation). [ x: of contents = λp :Ppty λq :Ppty λr : ] Ind Subst. c: Cxt N type =Q(r) : RecType [ z : par : ] Ind c : Cxt s in.vessel : Q(r). s app P(par).s app [s within : each.within(r.x, par.z)] After some steps of flattening and relabelling: glasses of contents wine = p cbase =λr :[y : Ind].[s 1 :r.c(wine)(r.y)] : Ppty [ z : [ x: λr : ] par : ] Ind Ind Subst c : Cxt. c: Cxt s 2 : r.c(wine)(r.x) s in.vessel : s 3 : par.c(glass)(par.z) s within : each.within(r.x, par.z) I.e. Individuated partition of wine such that each part of the partition is contained by a glass. 19/25 Container, contents and measures

Measure readings: a shift on a contents shift Evoked by either lexical or discourse context (singular verbal agreement with NP or comparison with a scale inconsistent with [ a contents (or container) ] reading) x: MEASURE = λp :Ppty λr :[n : R] λr : Ind Subst. d: Scale [ ] v: par 2 : Ind Subst c: Cxt R.n=Measure(r.x, r.d, P(par 2 )) : R [ ] x: MEASURE( glasses of container wine ) = λr :[n : R] λr : Ind Subst. d: Scale [ ] x: par 2 : Ind Subst c: Cxt p cbase =λr :[y : Ind].[s 1 :r.c(wine)(r.y)] : Ppty [ ] z : par : Ind c : Cxt R.n=Measure(r.x, r.d, ) : R s 2 : par 2.c(wine)(par 2.v) s in.vessel : s 3 : par.c(glass)(par.z) s within : each.within(par 2.v, par.z) Function from numbers n to property of individuals or substances that measure n with respect being wine, the contents of a glass on some scale (volume, calorific content etc.) 20/25 Container, contents and measures

Summary Predictions of the account for full pseudo-partitive NPs Measure readings of full pseudo-partitive NPs usually require a substantial contextual trigger and an interpretive effort on the part of the interpreter Why? because measure readings are derived from contents readings (a contents-to-measure shift is needed) Need discourse context or singular verbal agreement to force this shift. Accessibility hierarchy: cl-like concept (glass) container of / [pause] + N sg agreement / in + measure PP etc. measure Type clash resolved by shift to measure interpretation contents Type Clash 21/25 Container, contents and measures

Outline Introduction and plan Small case study: wine and beer Analysis Structure of pseudo-partitive NPs Semantic analysis of pseudo-partitive NPs in TTR CD + Mass Noun expressions: why are measure readings (usually) blocked

Sketching an explanation: What is different about CD + Mass Noun expressions? 1. Type mismatches are resolved by container or contents shifts. Type mismatches: CD + Mass Noun, and (sometimes) Mass Noun + PL. Agents must coerce the Mass N into a count N reading. Requires supplying additional concepts that are salient or conventional (e.g. concept for glass), and then type shifting this into a container or a contents reading modifier. Type mismatches (CD + Mass N and/or Mass N + PL) are resolved by shifting to a container or a contents reading 2. Cognitive burden No need to shift again Measure readings are highly context sensitive (require identifying the relevant dimension (and a scale) for measurement of contents) It is usually too much to: retrieve a container concept, shift it to a contents reading, identify a dimension for measurement (possibly with an associated scale), and then shift the contents reading into a measure reading relative to the dimension (scale). 22/25 Container, contents and measures

Accessibility hierarchy (coercion case) mass n concept (wine) count syntax / PL morphology Type Clash enumerate kinds Type clash resolved See: Sutton and Filip (2017) cl-like concept + mass n concept combine mass concept with CL-like concept container Type clash resolved contents Type clash resolved SG agreement; in + measure PP etc. Type Clash measure Resolving 2 type clashes = too much cognitive burden Only resolvable if really forced 23/25 Container, contents and measures

Summary Full pseudo-partitive NP CD+Mass N mass n concept (wine) count syntax / PL morphology Type Clash cl-like concept (glass) of / [pause] + N enumerate kinds Type clash resolved cl-like concept + mass n concept container sg agreement / in + measure PP etc. measure Type clash resolved by shift to measure interpretation contents Type Clash container Type clash resolved combine mass concept with CL-like concept SG agreement; in + measure PP etc. contents Type clash resolved Type Clash measure Resolving 2 type clashes = too much cognitive burden Only resolvable if really forced 24/25 Container, contents and measures

Conclusions New observations: Measures are formed from a complex N (glass of wine), not from just a CL on its own (glass) Measure interpretations of e.g., glass of wine are often not volume interpretations CD+Mass N constructions routinely seem to lack coerced measure interpretations If measure interpretations are derived from contents interpretations, we can derive the following correct predictions: Full pseudo-partitive NP CD+Mass N One type clash resolution to get to the measure interpretation Fewer measure than container/ contents interpretations Two type clash resolutions to get to the measure interpretation Hardly any measure interpretations Not predicted: Why it is harder to coerce wine than beer into container/contents interpretation 25/25 Container, contents and measures

Selected References I Robin Cooper. Type theory and semantics in flux. In R. Kempson, T. Fernando, and N. Asher, editors, Philosophy of Linguistics, Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, pages 271 323. Elsevier, 2012. Fred Landman. Predicate-argument mismatches and the adjectival theory of indefinites. In M. Coene and Y. d Hulst, editors, From NP to DP Volume 1: The Syntax and Semantics of Noun Phrases, pages 211 237. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, 2003. Fred Landman. Count Nouns Mass Nouns Neat Nouns Mess nouns. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6:1 67, 2011. Godehard Link. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretic approach. In Rainer Bäuerle, Urs Egli, and Arnim von Stechow, editors, Meaning, Use and the Interpretation of Language, pages 303 323. de Gruyter, Berlin, 1983.

Selected References II Susan Rothstein. Counting, measuring and the semantics of classifiers. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6:1 41, 2011. Peter R. Sutton and Hana Filip. Mass/count variation, a mereological, two-dimensional semantics. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition Logic and Communication, 11:1 45, 2016a. Peter R. Sutton and Hana Filip. Probabilistic mereological type theory and the mass/count distinction. Under review for JLM (proceedings of Type Theory and Lexical Semantics (TYTLES) workshop at ESSLLI 2015), 2016b. Peter R. Sutton and Hana Filip. Restrictions on subkind coercion in object mass nouns. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 21, page (To appear), 2017. Preprint available at: https://sites.google.com/site/sinnundbedeutung21/ proceedings-preprints.

Thank you very much for listening! Download these slides from: sfb991.uni-duesseldorf.de/en/c09/slides/